--------
How do humans first come to know simple facts about physical objects,
colours, minds and the rest?
--------
Core knowledge is real. Infants’ have unexpectedly sophisticated abilities concerning physical objects
and categorical colour properties (and much more) even from the first year of life.
--------
There is a gap between core knowledge and knowledge knowledge. It takes months
if not years between clear manifestations of core knowledge and knowledge knowledge.
Importantly,
--------
Crossing the gap involves social interactions, perhaps involving words.
--------
Having core knowledge of something does not involve having any knowledge knowledge at all.
Here I'm going to use the term ‘concept of X’ for that which enables one to have knowledge
of Xs.
How do we get from core knowledge to concepts?
--------
Core knowledge enables one to distinguish things. For example it enables on to distinguish
those things which are blue from those which are not;
it enables one to distinguish those events which are causal interactions from those
which are not;
it enables one to distinguish those sets which have two members from others;
and it enables one to distinguish different beliefs about the location of an object (say).
(Here I'm using core knowledge in the broad, schematic sense to refer to representations
which are knowledge-like but not knowledge.)
--------
I conjecture that core knowledge faciliates acquisition of the correct use of a word,
perhaps very slowly. The idea is that being able to discriminate things allows one to
apply a label to them.
Importantly we can discriminate without having concepts.
If one thought that all discrimination involved concepts, this picture would become circular.
--------
How does core knowledge enable one to correctly use words?
I think it modifies the overall phenomenal character of your experience,
typically by generating phenomenal expectations (which I called them perceptual expectations
earlier in this version of the course).
Tuning in to the perceptual expectations can take a long time, which is why there may be
a long interval between observing core knowledge and observing the correct use of words.
--------
I also conjecture that using the word facilitates concept acquisition.
Many people would probably agree.
But how does it do this?
My schematic suggestion is that using the word draws attention to all the things which are Xs.
The concept is acquired when you are struck by the question,
What do all these have in common?
(Clearly this is not an account of how thinking gets started at all; the appeal
to reflection should make this obvious.)
We have quite good evidence for this picture in the cases of colour and number,
and there is relevant evidence in the case of mindreading too. (Also speech:
phonological awareness is linked to literacy and the particulars of the written
language learnt, so that alphabetic languages give a different profile --- alphabet is
roughly labelling phonemes.)
The question we've been looking at last week is how children come to correctly
use words.
--------
This is about the step from discrimination to learning the correct use of a verbal label.
So there's you and you're observing sequence of stimuli and thanks to core knowledge
you're able to discriminate them.
--------
And now along comes another person. What are they doing? Nothing yet. But ...
--------
Oh look they're labelling stimuli.
So now the blue ones (say) are special. You respond to them in one way and the
other responds to them in her way, which is by labelling.
--------
Now you can observe that your responses are correlated with her responses.
So when you discriminate in a certain way, she applies the label.
Observing this correspondence enables you to learn the label (say).
This is triangulation roughly as Davidson describes it.
And having got this far you can ask yourself what all the things labelled
have in common.
--------
Core knowledge is real. Infants’ have unexpectedly sophisticated abilities concerning physical objects
and categorical colour properties (and much more) even from the first year of life.
There is a gap between core knowledge and knowledge knowledge. It takes months
if not years between clear manifestations of core knowledge and knowledge knowledge.
Importantly,
Crossing the gap involves social interactions, perhaps involving words.
--------
Gradually build up from understanding minds and actions to words.
*for bk: include \citep{meyer:2016_monitoring} on crawling infants’
(informative about relations between performance and observation)
--------
--------
When can infants first track goals to which actions are directed?
--------
Consider a much-replicated study by Woodward and colleagues.
--------
'Six-month-olds and 9-month-olds showed a stronger novelty response (i.e., looked longer) on new-goal trials than on new-path trials (Woodward 1998). That is, like toddlers, young infants selectively attended to and remembered the features of the event that were relevant to the actor’s goal.'
\citep[p.\ 153]{woodward:2001_making}
--------
Using a manipulation we’ll discuss later (‘sticky mittens’),
\citet{sommerville:2005_action} used this paradigm to show that even
three-month-olds can form expectations based on the goal of an action
(for another study with three-month-olds, see also \citealp{luo:2011_threemonthold}).
--------
I distinguish {goals} from {targets}.
The \emph{target} or \emph{targets} of an action (if any) are the things the towards which it is directed.
If kicking a football is the goal of an action, the football is its target.
To specify a target of an action is to partially specify one of its goals.
But more is required to fully specify a goal, of course.
--------
A goal typically involves a type of action---kicking rather than smashing, say---as well as manners of
action---discretely, firmly, and precisely, for example---and perhaps more besides.
For a process to \emph{track} a target of an action is for how that process unfolds to nonaccidentally
depend in some way on whether that thing is indeed a target of the action.
The studies we have considered so far focus on infants’ abilities to track the targets of actions.
--------
For a process to \emph{track} a target of an action is for how that process unfolds to nonaccidentally
depend in some way on whether that thing is indeed a target of the action.
The studies we have considered so far focus on infants’ abilities to track the targets of actions.
Given the liberal way I have defined tracking a goal, a process which tracks a target is thereby a process which tracks a goal. (The converse will often hold too, although there could be exceptions.)
It is conceivable that some types of processes \emph{merely} track targets: that is,
processes of this type only ever track goals in virtue of tracking targets.
The studies we have considered so far are consistent with the hypothesis that infants
are merely tracking targets in this sense.
--------
To answer this question, we would ideally have pairs of scenarios in which the target of an action
is kept constant while the type of action varies.
To the extent that subjects respond appropriately to the difference in type of action, we can be
confident that they can distinguish actions not just by their targets but also by their types.
This is illustrated here, where you are habituated to a grasping event and the test events are
(a) grasping but with novel kinematics (from a different angle), or (b) a novel goal event (pushing).
Unfortunately, as far as I know this has not yet been done.
But there are some studies which, although not intended to get at exactly the issue of whether
infants track goals and not just targets of actions, do indirectly shed light on this issue.
These studies demonstrate competence in goal-tracking from nine months of age, and give us no reason
to doubt that, in simple enough cases, infants might show competence in goal tracking much earlier.
\citet{Behne:2005dw} created just such pairs of contrasting scenarios.
In one of their contrasts, an experimenter holds a ball out for an infant to grasp and then
either ‘accidentally’ drops it or teasingly pulls it back.
So in each case there is a goal-directed action involving the ball, but in one case the goal
of the action is to pass the ball to the infant whereas in the other case the goal is to
tease the infant.
\citet[Study 2]{Behne:2005dw} found that nine-month-olds (but not six-month-olds)
consistently and appropriately discriminated between these scenarios by, for example,
banging more when the ball was ‘accidentally’ dropped than when it was teasingly retracted.
This and other research
(e.g. \citealp{ambrosini:2013_looking}) suggests that, at least from nine months of age,
infants can indeed distinguish both the type and target of a goal-directed action.
% \citet{ambrosini:2013_looking} is important: shows that type of grasp and not just target is tracked, implying that anticipatory looking is not merely perceptual animacy.
--------
Infants can track goals from nine months of age (or earlier).
--------
The question, of course, is how?
--------
--------
To more fully specify goal-tracking we need a theory that specifies
both the models and the processes involved in goal-tracking.
--------
Let me first specify the problem to be solved.
--------
As this illustrates,
some actions involving are purposive in the sense that
--------
among all their actual and possible consequences,
--------
there are outcomes to which they are directed
--------
In such cases we can say that the actions are clearly purposive.
--------
Note that it isn’t part of our job to track the mental states, such as intentions,
in virtue of which the outcome is a goal.
--------
What we are tracking here are just outcomes to which the action is directed,
not mental states.
--------
So planning is the process of moving from goals to means,
whereas tracking goes in the reverse direction, from means to goals.
But what is common to the two is the relation between means and goals.
In both cases, planning and goal-tracking, the means that are adopted should be a best available
way of bringing the goal about.
--------
Note that this is not exactly an answer to our question,
How can infants track goals from nine months of age (or earlier)?
It provides what Marr would call a computational description.
That is, it provides a function
from
facts about events and states of affairs that could be known without knowing which goals any
particular actions are directed to, nor any facts about particular mental states
to
one or more outcomes which are the goals of an action.
Providing this function explains how pure goal-tracking is possible in principle.
But what we want to know, of course, is how infants (and adults) actually compute this function.
If this is (roughly) the function which computationally describes pure goal tracking,
what are the representations and processes involved in pure goal tracking?
--------
An we need to know how they compute to which outcome a means is the best available.
--------
To more fully specify goal-tracking we need a theory that specifies
both the models and the processes involved in goal-tracking.
--------
The Simple View is a view about the PROCESSES involved ...
--------
\begin{quote}
Infants' (and adults') goal tracking depends on beliefs concerning relations which hold
quite generally between means and goals; and they identify particular goals by making
inferences from these beliefs plus their observations.
\end{quote}
Infants and adults engaged in goal-tracking reason about
to which outcome a means is the best available
in fundamentally the same way that you or I do when trying to work it out explicitly.
--------
[*TODO: illustrate with picture.]
--------
Irrespective of who endorses it, the Simple View is a good starting point for at least three reasons.
First, it involves postulating no novel psychological states, processes or systems.
(It does not entail the existence of a goal-tracking module, for example.)
Second, as just illustrated, it is a generalisation from cases in which its claim is known to apply.
Third, there are no published, suitably detailed accounts of any alternative.
So what if anything is wrong with the Simple View?
--------
The Teleological Stance is a proposed solution.
--------
To more fully specify goal-tracking we need a theory that specifies
both the models and the processes involved in goal-tracking.
The Simple View gives us this; but as usual we will see in the next section that it generates
incorrect predictions ...
--------
--------
Limits on performance are important because they provide clues about the nature
of the underlying processes.
--------
To explain this I have to step back and show you something interesting about
adults when they perform, and when they observe actions.
Performing actions (e.g. stacking blocks): you don't look at your hand but at
the block it will pick up, or, when holding a block, at the location where it will place a block.
That is, in acting the eyes move just ahead of the action.
--------
\citet{Flanagan:2003lm} showed that the same pattern occurs when adults observe another
acting.
In observing an action, the eyes move just ahead of the action.
This proactive gaze is important for our purposes because it can reveal goal-tracking ...
\citet{Flanagan:2003lm} showed that
‘patterns of eye–hand coordination are similar when performing and observing a block stacking task’.
--------
‘Positive relative times of the arrival of gaze at the goal area indicate that gaze precedes the agent’s arrival (predictive);
negative values indicate gaze arrival after agent arrival (non-predictive). Each age group is n = 12.
Error bars are s.e.m.’
GH : grasping hand; BH : back of hand; MC : mechanical claw
--------
Kanakogi \& Itakuar, 2011 show that abilities to grasp objects are correlated with
abilities to track the goal of a grasping action (as measured by proactive gaze).
x-axis is alpha, grasping angle. ‘An α angle value from 90 to 180° indicates that the infant
is engaged in a one-handed grasping action.’
‘The angle α is an index of the development of the onehanded grasping action and was
calculated by measuring the angle of a straight line de ned by the infant’s two hands (the
apex of the junction of the thumb and index nger) when crossed by an imaginary line
projecting frontally from the infant (Fig. 2b). If infants grasped for the objects with their
le hand, we reversed the red rightangled triangle from one side to the other side and
calculated the angle α in the same way. e angle α value of 90° corresponded to a perfect
alignment of the hands in a twohanded reach. erefore, the angle α value deviates from 90°
towards 180°, and bigger angle α value indicates more mature onehanded grasping. If the
angle α was over 90°, the infant was considered to be engaged in a onehanded grasping
action.’
--------
Further support for a link between action performance and goal tracking
comes from a developmental study by Ambrosini et al which studied whether proactive
gaze in infants is influenced by pre-shaping of the hand, and, in particular,
whether it is influenced by precision grips.
--------
By using no shaping (a fist), Ambrosini et al could treat sensitivity
to whole-hand grasp and precision grip separately.
--------
‘infants’ ability to perform specific grasping actions with fewer fingers directly predicted the degree with which they took advantage of the availability of corresponding pre-shape motor information in shifting their gaze towards the goal of others’ actions’ \citep[p.~6]{ambrosini:2013_looking}.
--------
Further, changing from a bodily action to the operation of a mechanical claw
(say) undermines the goal tracking effect.
So Kanakogi \& Itakuar, 2011 make two points:
(i) goal-tracking depends on action capabilities; and
(ii) only works for events involving biomechanically similar affectors
--------
Needham et al, 2002 showed that putting ‘sticky mittens’ on 3-month-old infants
(for 10-14 play sessions of 10 minutes each) resulted in their spending
more time visually and manually exporing novel objects.
--------
In this study, I think infants wore the mittens for just 200 seconds
(so the play sessions were much shorter than in Needhman et al, 2002).
--------
The observation was based on this study, which we saw earlier
--------
The results show that infants who played wearing the mittens first
were more attentive to the goal.
From at least three months of age, some of infants’ abilities to identify
the goals of actions they observe are linked to their abilities to perform
actions \citep{woodward:2009_infants}.
But one potential objection to this study concerns observation vs performance.
The infants who played wearing sticky mittens first had spent longer observing
actions by the time it came to the violation of expectations trial.
Could it be observation of action (including one’s own) rather than performance
that matters?
--------
nb something gets stuck to the mittens; it's not really grasping!
--------
To address this issue, \citet{sommerville:2008_experience} did a study in
which one group had observation while the other group had performance.
The participants were 10-month-old infants this time.
The materials were a bit different: so that training vs observation could
be as similar as possible with respect to the causal structure exposed,
there was a hook to get an object.
--------
The results show that infants with the training paid attention to the
distal goal (choice of toy) whereas those without paid attention to the
choice of cane.
--------
... or IMPAIR INDIRECTLY ...
Experiment 1 : shows that 6-month-old infants can distinguish a phonetic contrast
they have never heard before (one that occurs in Hindi but not their linguistic
environments.) (The contrast used was the Hindi dental /d/̪ versus retroflex /ɖ/
distinction.)
These graphs show a difference in mean looking time between cases in which phonemes
are alternated and cases in which they are not. (Iff infants distinguish, they should
find the alternating phonemes more interesting.)
Experiment 2: but not when they have a tongue-controlling dummy in their mouths
Experiment 3: but yes when they have a dummy which leaves the tongue free.
--------
I don’t think we have found strong evidence for this limit.
What we can conclude, more weakly, is that there is some limiting relation linking
goal-tracking and abilities to act.
--------
In infants (and adults),
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act.
Why is this true?
Why is goal-tracking in infants (and adult) limited by their abilities to act?
On the Simple View, goal tracking is a matter of thinking and reasoning about the
best means to perform an action.
On this View, there’s no obvious reason why
your goal-tracking should be limited by your abilities to act in this way.
Although I can’t jump over a house, I can perfectly well think about different ways
to do so and distinguish better and worse approaches, at least to some extent.
--------
--------
What follows rests on three background assumptions about the control of action.
First, I follow \citet{jeannerod_motor_2006} and others in rejecting the view that all motor representations specify only bodily configurations, joint displacements and end states.
Instead some motor representations specify outcomes to which actions are directed,
such as the grasping of a particular handle or the transporting of a given object.
Second, some motor processes involve computing means from ends and generating sensory expectations concerning the effects of actions \citep[e.g.][]{Wolpert:2003mg}.
Third, multiple means--ends computations can occur simultaneously, or at least rapidly enough for action preparation to involve selection on the basis of multiple means-ends computations
\citep[e.g.][]{wolpert_internal_1998}.
--------
It is now a familiar, if still interestingly controversial idea, that motor representation
leads a DOUBLE LIFE.
For it is involved not only in coordinating the performance of small-scale purposive
actions like reaching, grasping, placing and transporting but also in action observation.
--------
We know this in large thanks to the discovery of mirror neurons and their consequences.
‘(A) Congruence between the visual and the motor response of a mirror neuron. Unit 169 has a stronger
discharge during grasping to eat than during grasping to place, both when the action is executed and
when it is observed. Conventions as in Fig. 1. (B) Population-averaged responses during motor and
visual tasks (12).’
Suppose you are reaching for, grasping, transporting and then placing a pen. Performing even
relatively simple action sequences like this involves satisfying many constraints that cannot
normally be satisfied by explicit practical reasoning, especially if performance is to be rapid and
fluent. Rather, such performances require motor representations.
These representations are paradigmatically involved in preparing, executing and monitoring actions.%
\footnote{%
See \citet{wolpert:1995internal, miall:1996_forward, jeannerod:1998nbo, zhang:2007_planning}.
Note that motor representations sometimes occur in an agent who has prepared an action and is required (as it turns out) not to perform it: although she has prevented herself from acting, motor representations specifying the action persist, perhaps because they are necessary for monitoring whether prevention has succeeded \citep{bonini:2014_ventral}.
}
But they also live a double life. Motor representations concerning a particular type of action are
involved not only in performing an action of that type but also sometimes in observing one. That is,
if you were to observe Ayesha reach for, grasp, transport and then place a pen, motor representations
would occur in you much like those that would also occur in you if it were you---not Ayesha---who was
doing this.
Converging evidence for this assertion comes from a variety of methods and measures;
but I won’t mention any of that here.
--------
So we have to ask, What are those motor representations doing here?
And when you do ask that you find that, in adults, they appear to be facilitating
your abilities to track the goals of observed actions.
This is inspiration for the Motor Theory of Goal Tracking ...
--------
mTgt is an alternative to the Simple View.
The idea is that pure goal-tracking involves motor processes rather than thinking
and reasoning about goals.
But how could motor processes enable goal tracking?
--------
Goal-tracking is acting in reverse.
-- in action observation, possible outcomes of observed actions are represented
-- these representations trigger planning as if performing actions directed to the outcomes
-- such planning generates predictions
-- a triggering representation is weakened if its predictions fail
The result is that the only only outcomes to which the observed action is a means
are represented strongly.
There is evidence that a motor representation of an outcome can cause a determination of which movements are likely to be performed to achieve that outcome \citep[see, for instance,][]{kilner:2004_motor, urgesi:2010_simulating}. Further, the processes involved in determining how observed actions are likely to unfold given their outcomes are closely related, or identical, to processes involved in performing actions.
This is known in part thanks to studies of how observing actions can facilitate performing actions congruent with those observed, and can interfere with performing incongruent actions \citep{
brass:2000_compatibility,
craighero:2002_hand,
kilner:2003_interference,
costantini:2012_does}.
Planning-like processes in action observation have also been demonstrated by measuring observers' predictive gaze. If you were to observe just the early phases of a grasping movement, your eyes might jump to its likely target, ignoring nearby objects \citep{ambrosini:2011_grasping}. These proactive eye movements resemble those you would typically make if you were acting yourself \citep{Flanagan:2003lm}.
Importantly, the occurrence of such proactive eye movements in action observation depends on your
representing the outcome of an action motorically; even temporary interference in the observer's
motor abilities will interfere with the eye movements \citep{Costantini:2012fk}.
These proactive eye movements also depend on planning-like processes; requiring the observer to
perform actions incongruent with those she is observing can eliminate proactive eye movements
\citep{Costantini:2012uq}. This, then, is further evidence for planning-like motor processes in
action observation.
So observers represent outcomes motorically and these representations trigger planning-like processes
which generate expectations about how the observed actions will unfold and their sensory consequences.
Now the mere occurrence of these processes is not sufficient to explain why, in action observation,
an outcome represented motorically is likely to be an outcome to which the observed action is
directed.
To take a tiny step further, we conjecture that, in action observation, \textbf{motor representations of
outcomes are weakened to the extent that the expectations they generate are unmet}
\citep[compare][]{Fogassi:2005nf}.
A motor representation of an outcome to which an observed action is not directed is likely to
generate incorrect expectations about how this action will unfold, and failures of these
expectations to be met will weaken the representation.
This is what ensures that there is a correspondence between outcomes represented motorically in
observing actions and the goals of those actions.
--------
‘proactive gaze’ and ‘explicit judgement’ are variables whose values represent
whether there is a proactive gaze or explicit judgement, and what is it to or about.
Likewise, ‘motor process’ is a variable whose values represent ...
The lines depict how the variables are causally related. I’ve used thick and thin
lines informally, to indicate weaker and stronger influences.
--------
The dual-process theory of goal-tracking makes perfect sense of development.
It says that what we observe in six- and nine-month-olds is motor-based goal-tracking.
Presumably the more flexible, reasoning-based goal-tracking processes emerge some time
later in development.
--------
Motor Conjecture
In 9-month-olds,
all pure goal-tracking is explained by the Motor Theory;
--------
Infants can track goals from nine months of age (or earlier).
--------
In infants (and adults),
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act.
--------
Important that
mTgt is not an alternative to the Teleological Stance but to it plus the claim about reasoning.
Simple View and mTgt do not differ on the relation between means and goals that is to be
computed in pure goal-tracking.
The Simple View and mTgt differ only on what processes is responsible for identifying which outcome or
outcomes the observed means is a best available way of achieving.
--------
There’s just one small problem. It’s not quite true to say that
infants goal-tracking is limited by action ability.
Some of it is, but some of it isn’t ...
--------
--------
Earlier I mentioned this experiment, which shows that infants
fail to track goals involving things which would appear to them to be
biomechanically non-agent-like events.
But ...
--------
\#source 'research/teleological stance -- csibra and gergely.doc'
\#source 'lectures/mindreading and joint action - philosophical tools (ceu budapest 2012-autumn fall)/lecture05 actions intentions goals'
\#source 'lectures/mindreading and joint action - philosophical tools (ceu budapest 2012-autumn fall)/lecture06 goal ascription teleological motor'
When do human infants first track goal-directed actions and not just movements?
Here's a classic experiment from way back in 1995.
The subjects were 12 month old infants.
They were habituated to this sequence of events.
--------
There was also a control group who were habituated to a display like this
one but with the central barrier moved to the right, so that the action
of the ball is 'non-rational'.
--------
For the test condition, infants were divided into two groups. One saw a new action, ...
... the other saw an old action.
Now if infants were considering the movements only and ignoring information about the goal, the 'new action' (movement in a straight line) should be more interesting because it is most different.
But if infants are taking goal-related information into action, the 'old action' might be unexpected and so might generate greater dishabituation.
--------
You might say, it's bizarre to have used balls in this study, that can't show us anything about infants' understanding of action.
But adult humans naturally interpret the movements of even very simple shapes in terms of goals.
So using even very simple stimuli doesn't undermine the interpretation of these results.
--------
Consider a further experiment by \citet{Csibra:2003jv}, also with
12-month-olds. This is just like the first ball-jumping experiment
except that here infants see the action but not the circumstances in
which it occurs. Do they expect there to be an object in the way behind
that barrier?
--------
Here then is the puzzle about development that I mentioned this talk was about:
In infants under 10 months,
it appears that
some,
but not all,
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act.
Let me recap how we got here and why this is puzzling.
I started by asking, How 9-month-olds track can goals?
The Simple View offers one answer:
the principles comprising the Teleological Stance are things they know or believe, and they are able
to track goals by making inferences from these principles.
I suggested that the Simple View should be rejected because it cannot explain why infants’
abilities to track goals are limited by their abilities to perform actions.
At least, mTga provides a better alternative to the Simple View.
According to mTga,
Infants’ pure goal-tracking depends on the double life of motor processes.
mTga correctly predicts that infants’ pure goal-tracking should be limited by infants’
abilities to act ...
--------
But, unfortunately, there appear to be cases in which infants’ pure goal-tracking
is not limited by their abilities to act, and this is contrary to mTga.
The puzzle, then, to explain how infants can track goals if neither the Simple View
nor mTga is correct.
Even worse,
there’s another, apparently unrelated puzzle to explain too ...
--------
Daum et al created a modified version of Woodward’s paradigm which allowed them to measure
both anticipatory looking and dishabituation.
where researchers have measured two different responses to a single
scenario, anticipatory looking and either dishabituation or pupil dilation.
Generally, they appear to find evidence for goal tracking in dishabituation
or pupil dilation but not in anticipatory looking.
(This is true of Daum et al, 2012; and Gredeback and Melinder, 2010.)
Why the discrepancy?
This is another question we can’t answer with the Motor Theory of Goal
Tracking.
--------
[skip -- just here in case need for discussion; shows that anticipatory looking
to cartoon fish takes years to develop]
--------
Here then is another puzzle about development:
In infants under 10 months,
it appears that
some,
but not all,
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act ...
... and that goal-tracking sometimes manifests in dishabitution or pupil dilation but not proactive gaze.
The \textbf{second puzzle} is how to explain, in a principled way, why there should be discrepancies
between these measures. We cannot do this by invoking mTgt because on mTgt, proactive gaze is a
case in which goal-tracking is paradigmatically manifest.
--------
I want to respond by arguing that not everything which appears to be goal-tracking in infants
actually is goal-tracking.
--------
So the puzzle is merely apparent.
The appearance is due to the fact that we do not carefully enough distinguish tracking
the target of an action from tracking the goal of an action.
--------
--------
\emph{perceptual animacy},
the detection by broadly perceptual processes of animate objects and their targets.
--------
Evidence for the existence of perceptual animacy comes from a variety of studies
where adults are given a simple visual task such as identifying which circle is the ‘wolf’
and which the ‘sheep’, or, in another experiment, moving the sheep around in order to
avoid being caught by the wolf.
It is also possible to examine how having a sheep and a wolf affects how attention is allocated by
measuring how well participants can detect probes placed on different shapes.
The literature on perceptual animacy mostly confounds it with goal tracking.
But there are two key differences.
First, perceptual animacy is a broadly
perceptual phenomenon.
Second,
the perceptual detection of animacy is clearly distinct from goal tracking
for it involves detecting relations between objects in motion rather than
outcomes to which actions are directed.
Relatedly, it does not involve sensitivity to the type of action.
And the perceptual detection of animacy appears to depend on simple cues
and heuristics and is unlikely to be correctly described by the
Teleological Stance.
So perceptual animacy does not involve tracking goals to which an action is
directed: it is a matter of tracking objects to which animate movements are
directed.
--------
\emph{{perceptual animacy}},
the detection by broadly perceptual processes of animate objects and their targets.
To illustrate, consider a groundbreaking experiment by \citet[experiment 1]{gao:2009_psychophysics}.
Adults were shown a display which contained some moving circles.
In some cases the circles moved independently of each other, but in other cases there was a ‘wolf’
which chased a ‘sheep’ with varying degrees of subtlety.
The adults’ task was simply to detect the presence of a wolf.
\citeauthor{gao:2009_psychophysics} established that adults can do this providing the chasing is not too subtle.
In further experiments, they also showed that adults’ abilities to perceptually detect chasing
depend on several cues including whether the chaser ‘faces’ its target (‘directionality’) and how
directly the chaser approaches its target (‘subtlety’).
The detection of animacy appears to be a broadly perceptual phenomena since it depends on areas of
the brain associated with vision and influences how perceptual attention is allocated
\citep{scholl:2013_perceiving} irrespective of your beliefs and intentions
\citep{buren:2016_automaticity}.
--------
[This comparison is a bit confused because pure-goal tracking is the kind of thing
that can be (and is) achieved by way of different mechanisms (e.g. reasoning; motor processes),
whereas perceptual animacy is a mechanism.]
The perceptual detection of animacy resembles goal tracking, for it involves detecting a relation
between a chaser and its target.
However the perceptual detection of animacy is clearly distinct from goal tracking.%
\footnote{%
Contrast \citet{schlottmann:2010_goal,Scholl:2000eq} who all claim that perceptual animacy is a matter of, or involves, tracking goals.
}
For one thing, it involves detecting relations between objects in motion rather than outcomes to
which actions are directed.
Relatedly, it does not involve sensitivity to the type of action.
Finally, the perceptual detection of animacy appears to depend on simple cues and heuristics and is
unlikely to be correctly described by the Teleological Stance.
For these reasons, we should distinguish the perceptual detection of animacy from tracking goals to which actions are directed.
--------
To illustrate, we have to recognise that, in adults,
there are multiple processes
involved in tracking actions, which are differently affected by changes in
context, and which probably have different affects on different kinds of responses to
observed and anticipated actions.
Here is a rough guess about how things look IN ADULTS.
--------
Motor Conjecture Revised
In 9-month-olds,
all pure goal-tracking is explained by the Motor Theory;
appearances that goal-tracking is not limited by their abilities to act
are due to perceptual animacy.
--------
Predictions
Where 9-month-olds appear to be tracking goals
in ways not limited by their abilities to act,
they will be subject to signature limits of perceptual animacy
(e.g. subtlety, directionality);
and the processes underlying their abilities will be broadly perceptual.
--------
what’s already in infants ...
--------
How does the conjecture help with the puzzles about development?
In infants under 10 months,
it appears that
some,
but not all,
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act ...
... and that goal-tracking sometimes manifests in dishabitution or pupil dilation but not proactive gaze.
The second puzzle was a dissociation between dishabituation and pupil dilation on the one
hand and proactive gaze on the other.
The conjecture I have formulated suggests a solution: perhaps perceptual animacy is sometimes
responsible for pupil dilation and dishabituation; but never responsible for proactive gaze.
--------
The first puzzle was the appearance of cases of goal-tracking in infancy which is not
limited by infants’ abilities to act.
The conjecture I have proposed suggests a solution to this too: those cases
are underpinned by perceptual animacy and so not genuine cases of goal-tracking at all.
--------
Pupil dilation at 6 and 12-months of age; unlike proactive gaze, it does not
correlate with experience of being fed; but it isn’t plausibly perceptual animacy either.
(Why would perceptual animacy predict a difference between spoon going to mouth or hand?)
Instead it may be a consequence of associative learning about the typical sequence
of chunks of actions.
--------
First conclusion: there is a developmental puzzle about goal tracking
In infants under 10 months,
it appears that
some,
but not all,
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act ...
... and that goal-tracking sometimes manifests in dishabitution or pupil dilation but not proactive gaze.
The \textbf{second puzzle} is how to explain, in a principled way, why there should be discrepancies
between these measures. We cannot do this by invoking mTgt because on mTgt, proactive gaze is a
case in which goal-tracking is paradigmatically manifest.
--------
I defended this conjecture (partially)
Motor Conjecture Revised
In 9-month-olds,
all pure goal-tracking is explained by the Motor Theory;
appearances that goal-tracking is not limited by their abilities to act
are due to perceptual animacy.
This conjecture is quite bold, but I think it’s one worth betting on partly because,
as I suggested, it generates readily testable predictions.
This conjecture also has another virtue.
Goal-tracking is so fundamental to social cognition and joint action that it is
likely to depend on a rich mix of many kinds of processes, including associative learning.
We need ways to identify these processes, to distinguish their limits and to understand their
synergies.
Distinguishing motor processes which support goal-tracking by realising the Teleological Stance
from perceptual animacy is a step towards meeting this need.
--------
Emphasize: (1) that they understand action is important because we can use it
to build an account of how you get from core knowledge to knowledge knowledge
--------
Emphasize: (2) that their understanding of action does not involve
knowledge is important because it allows us to invoke it without
assuming capacities for any knowledge at all on the part of the infant.
(And because it leaves us with a question about how infants get from
core knowledge of action to knowledge of action.)
--------
Key thing is that we don’t have to postulate knowledge of goals;
earliest goal-tracking abilities can be invoked to explain the developmental emergence of knowledge
(of goals, and of other things).